Thursday, May 24, 2012

Treating Terrorism Like The Disease It Is


 “Treating Terrorism Like The Disease it Is”
by
F. H. Fox



            Attempting to create a single definition for terrorism is a bit like a doctor saying all ailments of the human body are caused by the same thing, and as such, the human body should always be treated for those ailments in the same way. Instead, I propose that there should be multiple definitions of terrorism because terrorism can then be diagnosed and fought using vastly different techniques. To do so would be beneficial for all humankind. Therefor, I will discuss and create a definition what is perhaps the largest area of collective terrorism, religiously motivated groups using violence to change the status quo.
            After September 11, 2001, the Bush administration’s decision to define the enemy who attacked the United States of America as a specific group of terrorists seemed like a logical course of action, but then the Bush government abruptly changed its policy and suddenly lumped the nation’s entire response, "Into a single, undifferentiated enemy undermined efforts to devise an effective strategic strategy."[1] This proved ultimately problematic because it shifted the needed resources to deal many different groups and individuals collectively identified as terrorists. With the limited U.S. resources stretched to dangerously low levels, President Bush's conception of the threat produced a flawed strategic response that continues to plague the national defense of the United States of America today. Therefore, as Graham Allison pointed out, "When initial conceptions of the enemy are flawed, the policies that follow will be similarly confused: objectives will be inflated and imprecise, resources will be misallocated, and the scope of the response, both geographically and moral, will be diffused."[2]
            Furthermore, attempting to eradicate terrorism by using one description to define what terrorism is, is a lot like producing a “Grand Unification Theory” in particle physics; for example, while physicists seem to have a solid core understanding of how everything works together, as the scale changes to ever more precise measurements, their understanding breaks down and uncertainty prevails.[3] The same thing can then be said of terrorism. For example, while political scientists seem to have an overall understanding of terrorism, like physicists, when pressed for ever more precise definitions of terrorism, political scientists fail to deliver as the scale of investigation becomes increasingly more precise. Consequently, while this short paper cannot hope to attempt to produce a single unified theory of terrorism, it will examine one aspect of terrorism while attempting to answer the question, “When does religious violence become terrorism?”
            First, it is abundantly clear that not all religious violence is terrorism. Throughout history, numerous examples of religious groups doing violent things are not defined using the word terrorism. One primary example that comes to mind is the fifteenth century Mayans. No political scientist today would consider the Mayans people terrorists for a variety of reasons. It was state sponsored, it did not attempt to produce change, and the Mayan violence was normally directed towards the enemy who they captured. In a second example, it is unlikely a nonsectarian group using violence would be associated with religious violence. Lastly, the “lone wolf,” with one possible  exception that will be discussed later, is a person who hears command directed voices, even if he is part of a religious group, is generally not considered a terrorist.             
            So what is religiously based violence? While David Bromley does not specifically address the question, he does state, "By collective violence I refer to acts committed by individual in the name of some religious movement or the acts committed against religious individuals or movements by agents of social control and legitimated by some organizational purpose."[4] In that way, Bromley’s definition quantifies the violence using the word “collective” makes it clear that any definition of religious terror must have collective action. Additionally, to Bromley, it would seem that it is group behavior that mitigates or propels individuals into action or inaction. In that way, Bromley states leadership is ultimately important, especially when the group has reached its apex of development. Only when the leader feels he is losing control over the movement’s destiny will he, “Authorize or guide the use of force.” At this point, the group may be considered radicalized, and either harm others or themselves. Examples of external violence includes Solar Temple and Aum Shinrikyo, “Whose leaders gave direct orders to initiate violence.” Internal violence that ultimately was directed towards its own membership included Jim Jones’ White Night Drills, and Marshall Applewhite’s Heaven’s Gate. In both cases, members killed themselves and in some cases, each other.[5] 
            The question then becomes whether all religious cults, when their charismatic leaders feel threatened, have the propensity to become violent? Mark Juergensmeyer seems to think so. He stated that of the thirty most dangerous groups listed in 1998 by the U.S. Secretary of State Madeleine Albright, over half were religious. However, he then fails to point out many of the thirty violent groups were not religious. Furthermore, Juergensmeyer does not mention any larger study of violent groups, or what those percentages would be. For example, of the top one thousand most dangerous groups, how many would be considered religiously motivated? Even so, Juergensmeyer is correct when he claimed most people feel that religion should provide tranquility and peace, not terror. “Yet in many of these cases, religion supplied not only the ideology, but also the motivation and the organizational structure for the perpetrators."[6] However Juergensmeyer also points out one of the more problematic issues concerning terrorism, “Whether or not one uses “terrorist” to describe violent acts depends on wether one thinks that the acts are warranted.” For example, if the world is at peace and violence occurs, then it might be considered terrorism, but if the world is at war then the violence would considered legitimate.[7] However, from the point of view of the violent instigator, while the world may consider him a terrorist, he may see himself as a soldier if he thought his group at war. If so, then in his mind, his violent actions become justified and legitimate courses of action.
            Jessica Stern seems to agree. She used the Kalfan Khamis Mohamed bombing at the American Embassy at Tanzania to illustrate the point. Mohamed told the FBI in 1999 that he even though he had been caught, he thought the operation had been a success because since the bomb worked, it sent a message to America and kept American officials preoccupied with the investigation. Furthermore, he stated that if he had not been caught, he would have continued participate in the jihad against America. If released, he vowed to bomb Americans again. However, Mohamed also, “Wanted Americans to understand he and his fellow warriors are not crazy, gun-wielding people, but are fighting for a cause.”[8] In Mohamed’s case, this religiously motivated bombing was choreographed by a large religiously motivated group called Al Qaeda. However, that raises one of the more troubling aspects to discussing the religious ramifications of terrorism, whether the charismatic leadership of groups prone to violence may have one agenda while the people carrying out the acts an entirely different one.
            From Mohamed’s trial we can see there seems to be four levels of hierarchy, but only the lowest of the tier, those who are not even official Al Qaeda members that provide the fodder for suicide missions.[9] That would seem to establish, at least of Al Qaeda, that the people blowing themselves up, because they are not full members, may not agree with their leadership. If so, that may also indicate the suicide bombers are either more or less religiously and politically motivated then their leadership. More so, demonstrates they are more devoted to their religion than the leadership. In that case, religion is simply a means to an end for the leadership. However, if suicide bomber are really less devoted to religion than their leaders, then the opposite may be true. Only by making thorough studies of individual groups may an answer be found, but only for that one group because every group is different.
            However, not everyone agrees that religion even plays an important role in violence and terrorist activities. Worse yet, attempting to declare what constitutes a religion may be equally problematic. For example, William T. Cavanaugh indicates that Western nations cannot afford to allow religion to gain power because the changing dichotomy could potentially be problematic for national security. Specifically, he wrote:
Religion-and-violence arguments serve a particular need for their consumers in the West. These arguments are part of a broader Enlightenment narrative that has invented a dichotomy between the religious and the secular and constructed the former as an irrational and dangerous impulse that must give way in public to rational, secular forms of power. In the West, revulsion toward killing and dying in the name of one's religion is one of the principal means by which we become convinced that killing and dying in the name of the nation-state is laudable and proper. The myth of the religious violence also provides secular social orders with a stock character, the religious fanatic, to serve as enemy.[10]

In other words, Cavanaugh claims because secular nations cannot directly use religion as a way to motivate its people, but instead must uses religion to motivate indirectly, as a kind of mirror to convince its people that it is perfectly acceptable to die either for one’s country or die for one’s religion.
            So who is right? Are people motivated by religion to commit violent acts on the orders of charismatic leaders who feel they are loosing control over the direction their group is taking, or are religiously motivated people naturally drawn to people who have violent tendencies? The only way to decide is to continue examining ideas that will lead to a specific definition for religious terrorism. In doing so, we must now attempt to find a reasonable definition of religious violence?
            By comparing Pape and Abrahms and Tilly, it seems likely that likely answer must be somewhere between all the extremes. For example, while Pape and Abrahms argue about rational and social ideas, others like Tilly, Gurr, and Stern argue for different ideas why some people may be prone to either be violent, or be willing to join violent groups. While this may make it easy to expand this paper to include ever widening areas of thought for clarity, for the purposes of brevity, they must be excluded. Instead, I shall make use of their ideas along with the works already sited to make the case for my own definition of religious terror.
            First, as Cavanaugh stated it may in the interest of the West to convince its own people that religiously motivated terror and violence is the normal outcome of religious extremists and even fundamentalism because then it may be easier to get people to fight for the sovereignty of the nation. If that is so, then the created definition used for religious violence must be very specific, so as not to become a political motivator against all religious organizations, especially towards newly formed cults that have no violent tendencies. However, in doing so, we also must not forget that some religious leaders become violent, and may later direct their followers towards a path of violence later, even when in the beginning, there was no violent tendencies in the group. Second, when formulating the definition, we must remember the leaders directing the violence may not always agree with the people doing the violence, or vice versa. That means there may be the need to have a multipart definition to consider each tier of the violent religious group.             
           So now, having been given several important ideas what religious terrorism is, it should be possible to come up with a specific definition what religious terrorism is, and then compare it to existing debates. The definition must first include the idea of collectivism. As mentioned earlier, there is a “Lone Wolf” terrorist that must be identified for this definition. It is only when a “Lone Wolf” has gained control over a religious group through charismatic leadership, often telling his group that he communicates directly with God, that the “Lone Wolf” can then use his status to direct the religious group toward violent ends. So that means besides collectivism, the definition of religious terrorism must include charismatic leadership. Additionally, the religious group must want change. From the Mayan example, we saw that the Mayan leadership was more interested in keeping the status quo than changing the climate or government in any way. Lastly, we examined the use of religion itself by saying the definition of religious terrorism may not be a secular movement.
            So for the sake of argument, my definition of religious terrorism is the following, “Religious Terrorism is any violent act made by any collective religious group designed to change the status quo for either the members themselves, or others. The religious group must be led a charismatic leader, and that person must be religiously motivated. Lastly, religious terrorism must use violence to help create that change of status quo regardless of who the intended targets were. Unlike many other definitions of terrorism, I see no reason to differentiate between combatants and noncombatants as the targets of the intended violence of religious groups because in many cases, the religious person instigating the violence makes no differentiation.
            So now, let us examine one specific religion, and see if my definition holds up under scrutiny by analyzing the following debate, “Does Islam play a unique role in modern religious terrorism?”[11] McCarthy thinks it does, while Gerges disagrees. McCarthy claims visions of violence permeates the Western world from Muslims. He wrote the Islam provided the spiritual motivation for violent jihads, or religious wars.  He also states this is not well understood by the West and claims this violent movement has been growing in strength for centuries. Using just those first few ideas, it would seem that McCarthy would not support my definition because, as he argues, the violence has been going on for centuries. If true, that means there can be no single charismatic leader who has led Islam for such long time, seemingly invalidating my definition of “Religious Terrorism.”[12] However, Gerges disagrees and states Islam is not to blame. He claims moderation and tolerance already predominates the world wide Muslim communities. Instead, he points out it is the very nature of Islam that creates the problem and claims it is only a very small minority of Muslims who condone or engage in violence. In turn, Gerges would seem to validate my argument that it takes a charismatic leader to motivate his people to violence in the attempt to produce a religiously motivated outcome through violent acts and that Islam itself cannot be considered “Religious Terrorism” any more than Christianity can be blamed for its brand of terror throughout the Columbian Exchange or the Protestant Reformation. Only individual leaders using religion as a method to motivate followers to violence can be considered candidates for religious terrorism.[13]
            In conclusion, attempting to create a single definition for all terrorism is folly. Only by examining every aspect of terrorism in a concrete and scientific way can we hope to finally eradicate violence associated with all groups. However, to do so means multiple definitions of terrorism must be produced to deal with each kind of terrorism. Terrorism itself cannot be diagnosed or fought using singe techniques anymore than doctors can fight individual ailments in the human body with a single aspirin. Only by producing specific definitions for each kind of terrorism can we possibly hope to rid humankind of its’ plight.


[1] Stuart Gottlieb ed. Debating Terrorism and Counterterrorism: Conflicting Perspectives on Causes, Contexts, and Responses, (Washington, D.C.: CQ Press, 2010), page x.
[2] Stuart Gottlieb ed., Debating Terrorism and Counterterrorism: Conflicting Perspectives on Causes, Contexts, and Responses, page xi.
[3] Lisa Randall, Knocking on Heaven’s Door, (New York, Collins, 2011), pages xii-xxii.
[4] James R. Lewis, ed. Violence and New Religious Movements, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), page 27.
[5] James R. Lewis, ed. Violence and New Religious Movements, pages 24-25.
[6] Juergensmeyer, Mark. Terror in the Mind of God: The Global Rise of Religious Violence, (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2000), pages 5-6.
[7] Juergensmeyer, Mark. Terror in the Mind of God: The Global Rise of Religious Violence, (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2000), pages 8-9.
[8] Stern, Jessica. Terror in the Name of God: Why Religious Militants Kill, (New York: Harpers-Collins, 2003), pages 244-245.
[9] Stern, Jessica. Terror in the Name of God: Why Religious Militants Kill, (New York: Harpers-Collins, 2003), page 249.
[10] Cavanaugh, William T. The Myth of Religious Violence: Secular Ideology and the Roots of Modern Conflict, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), pages 4-5.
[11] Stuart Gottlieb, ed. Debating Terrorism and Counterterrorism: Conflicting Perspectives on Causes, Contexts, and Responses. (Washington, D.C.: CQ Press, 2010), pages 101-102.
[12] Stuart Gottlieb, ed. Debating Terrorism and Counterterrorism: Conflicting Perspectives on Causes, Contexts, and Responses. (Washington, D.C.: CQ Press, 2010),  pages 105-115.
[13] Stuart Gottlieb, ed. Debating Terrorism and Counterterrorism: Conflicting Perspectives on Causes, Contexts, and Responses,  pages 115 - 130.

No comments:

Post a Comment